Critical Thinking Chapter 10

Tài liệu học tập môn Critical Thinking tại Trường Đại học Quốc tế, Đại học Quốc gia Thành phố Hồ Chí Minh. Tài liệu gồm 18 trang giúp bạn ôn tập hiệu quả và đạt điểm cao! Mời bạn đọc đón xem! 

lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
1
Lecture Notes © 2008 McGraw Hill Higher 1
Education
Propositional logic
It is often difficult to determine whether a long and
complex argument is valid or invalid just by reading it.
Example:
If the Democrat loses the Senate race, the Republicans
will have a majority in the Senate.
If the Republicans have a majority in the Senate, the
Senate will vote down the new bill.
It is not the case that the Senate will vote down the
new bill or the Democrat will lose the Senate race.
So, it is not the case that if the Democrat does not lose,
the Senate will not vote down the new bill
2
Critical Thinking
Chapter 10
A Little Propositional Logic
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
2
Symbolization
Propositional logic is the way to symbolize the parts of
arguments so that we can analyze the whole arguments
for validity.
When you symbolize an argument, you represent its
simple statements with single letters, and then represent
the relationship between them (that the argument
suggests) with symbols.
3
Symbolization
Example: If Bush won we’re all going to die. Bush won.
Therefore we are all going to die.
Where:
b = Bush won
d = We’re all going to die
The argument gets symbolized like this:
1. b d
2. b
3. d
” means “Therefore”
4
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
3
Conjunction and validity
When two simple statements are conjoined with
an
“and,” we call it a “conjunction.”
We represent each statement as a simple letter,
and represent the “and” with an “&.” Example:
“Tina is tall and Sarah is tall.” gets symbolized like
this: p & q p = Tina is tall
q = Sarah is tall
5
Other words for “and”
If you see any of the following words, treat them like
“and” and symbolize the statement with an “&”:
but, yet, while, whereas, although, though, however.
They are different in meanings, but functionally
similar.
Note: What letter you give it really doesn’t matter, just
as long as you are consistent (use the same letter for
that statement every time) and don’t use the same
letter for two different statements in the same
argument.
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
4
6
Other words for “and”
Be warned: not every statement with “and” in it is
compound.
Example: The Knicks and Bulls are playing each other.
This is not expressing the facts that each team is
playing…
Mistake: The Knicks are playing and the Bulls are
playing (i.e., k & b).
…it is expressing the single fact that the two teams
are playing each other.
So it would just get a single letter, for instance, “e.”
7
Truth Tables
When evaluating validity, you don’t worry
about the truth value of the statements you
are symbolizing.
But each statement is either true or false (you
just don’t know which).
Truth Tables allow you to evaluate statements
and arguments without knowing truth values
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
5
by representing all possible truth value
combinations.
8
Truth Tables
Recall, we symbolized “Tina is tall and Sarah is tall” as
“p&q”.
We don’t know if they are or not, but we can represent all
possibilities this way:
p
q
p&q
----------
----------
---------
-
T
T
T
T
F
F
F
T
F
F
F
F
Notice: what “p&q means is “both p and q are true.This means that, unless both p and
q are true, “p&q” will not be true. That is why, above, p&q has a T only on the row on
9
which both p and q both have a T as well.
Using Truth Tables to Examine
Validity
Since….
…an argument is invalid only when it is possible for its
premises to be true and the conclusion false… …and
since truth tables show us all possible truth values
…we can use truth tables to evaluate validity.
We use them to determine all the possible truth
values, and then look for a row where all the
premise are true but the conclusion is false. If
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
6
we find one, the argument is invalid If there is
no such row, the argument is valid.
10
Example
(1) Tina is tall.
(2) Sarah is tall.
(3) Therefore, Tina and Sarah are tall.
Symbolized: p, q. q.
First, represent all the statement letters and their truth values.
Notice:
First row: two T’s, two F’s,
Second row: one T, one F (repeat)
11
Example
Then, add the premises and the conclusion.
p
p*
q*
p&q (C)
------
----------
----------
----------
T
T
F
p
q
-----
-
------
T
T
T
F
F
T
F
F
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
7
F
12
Example
Then, add the truth values.
p
q
p*
q*
p&q (C)
------
------
----------
----------
----------
T
T
T
T
T
T
F
T
F
F
F
T
F
T
F
F
F
F
F
F
13
Example
Then look for rows where the premises are all true, and see if the
conclusion is false on those rows. If there is such a row, then the
argument is invalid. In this case, the only row with all true
premises is one in which the conclusion is also true. Thus, the
argument is valid.
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
8
p
q
p*
q*
p&q (C)
-----
-
-----
-
---------
-
---------
-
----------
T
T
T
T
T
T
F
T
F
F
F
T
F
T
F
F
F
F
F
F
Valid
14
More Examples
1. Grass is green.
2. Therefore, grass is green and the sky is blue.
Symbolized: g g & s
Shows
it
to be invalid
Since, on the second
row, the premise is
true but the conclusion is false, the argument is
15
invalid.
g
s
g*
g&s (c)
------
------
------
------
T
T
T
T
T
F
T
F
F
T
F
F
F
F
F
F
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
9
Negation
We can easily represent “negated statements
with a “~” (tilde).
If “Sarah is tall” is “p” “Sarah is not tall” is
“~p” On a truth table:
anywhere p has a T
~p will have an F
16
Example:
(1) Tina is not Tall, but Sarah is tall. So, Tina is not tall.
Symbolized: ~p, q ~p
p
q
~p*
q*
~p (C)
-----
-
-----
-
---------
-
---------
-
---------
-
T
T
F
T
F
T
F
F
F
F
F
T
T
T
T
Valid
F
F
T
F
T
The argument is valid. The only row on which both premises are true is a row on which
the conclusion is also true. 17
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
10
Another example
Argument: Frank does not drive a truck. Therefore,
Frank doesn’t drive a truck and Vinny doesn’t drive a
minivan. Symbolized: ~f ~f & ~v
f
v
~v
---
---
---
T
T
F
T
F
T
F
T
F
F
F
T
Argument is invalid. Row 3 is an example of a row with true premises but a false 18
conclusion.
Whole statement negations
Not only can individual statements be negated:
~p
Compound statements can be too: ~(p&q)
Since “p&q” means “Both p and q are true”
“~(p&q)” means “It is false that both p and q are
true.”
19
~f & ~v) (c
(
~f*
)
----------
----------
F
f
F
f
F
f
F
t
T
t
F
f
T
t
T
t
invalid
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
11
Whole statement negations
But don’t distribute (like in math): ~(p&q) is
not the same as (~p & ~q)
Why?
~(p&q) means they are not both true (at least
one is false)
(~p & ~q) means they are both false
20
Proof: ~(p&q) ≠ (~p & ~q)
p
q
~p
~q
p&q
~ (p&q)
~p & ~q
----
----
----
----
----
----
-----
T
T
F
F
T
F
F
T
F
F
T
F
T
F
F
T
T
F
F
T
F
F
F
T
T
F
T
T
21
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
12
Truth tables with 3 variables
(set up)
Notice:
Third column, one T, one F (repeat)
Second column, two T’s, Two F’s (repeat) First column,
four T’s, four F’s
22
p
q
r
----
----
----
T
T
T
T
T
F
T
F
T
T
F
F
F
T
T
F
T
F
F
F
T
F
F
F
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
13
Argument: ~(p&q), (~q&r) ~p
Disjunctions (or statements)
“Frank is angry or Hank is tired.” gets
symbolized: a v t
(To make things easier, don’t ever use the letter “v”
to symbolize a simple statement.) Exclusive
and inclusive “or”:
Exclusive or: “a or b” means “a or b, but not both.”
Inclusive or: “a or b” means “at least a or b, but
maybe both.”
The convention is to use the inclusive sense. So….
25
24
p
q
r
~(p&q)*
(
~q & r
)*
~p (c)
---
-----------
----------------
---
------------
---
F
T
T
T
f
t
F
t
F
T
T
F
F
f
t
F
f
F
T
T
F
T
f
t
T
t
F
T
F
T
F
f
t
F
f
F
T
F
T
T
f
f
F
t
T
T
F
F
T
f
f
F
f
T
F
T
F
T
f
t
T
t
T
F
F
F
T
t
f
F
f
T
Shows it
is invalid
Even
though
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
14
Disjunction truth tables
p
q
pvq
---
---
----
T
T
T
T
F
T
F
T
T
F
F
F
26
Argument: pvq p
27
p (C)
p
q
pvq*
---
---
----
----
T
T
T
T
T
F
T
T
F
T
T
F
F
F
F
F
Invalid
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
15
Be careful with negations of
disjunctions
Frank is angry or Hank is tired. a v t
Frank is not angry or Hank is tired. ~a v t
Frank is not angry or Hank is not tired. ~a v ~t
It’s not the case that Frank is angry or Hank is tired.
~(a v t)
Neither is Frank angry nor is Hank tired. ~(a v t)
These last two are the same as “Frank is not angry and
Hank is not tired.”
(~a & ~t)
28
Proof: ~(pvq) ~p&~q
p
q
~(pvq)
~p&~q
---
---
--------
--------
-
T
T
F
t
fF
f
T
F
F
t
fF
t
F
T
F
t
tF
f
F
F
T
f
tT
t
29
look they match
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
16
Conditional (if,
then) statements
“If it rained then the ground is wet.”
Where:
r = it rained
w = the ground is wet r w
“r” is the antecedent
“wis the consequent
Lecture Notes © 2008 McGraw Hill Higher 30
Education
Conditional truth tables
Truth table is tricky. “pq” means
“every time p is true, q is true.”
Or “when p is true, q is true.”
So, only when the antecedent is true
and the
consequent false, is it the
case that the conditional is false.
If this confuses you, don’t worry… It is
confusing. Just remember it.
31
p
q
pq
---
---
------
T
T
T
T
F
F
F
T
T
F
F
T
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
17
Be careful with negation and
conditionals
If it did not rain, then the game was played.
~rp
If it did not rain, then the game was not
played.
~r ~p
It is not the case that, if it rained then the
game was played.
~(rp)
These all have different meanings.
32
Be careful with negation and
conditionals
p
q
pq
~pq
~p~q
~(pq)
--
-
---
-----
--------
---------
----------
T
T
T
fT
t
fT
f
F
t
T
F
F
fT
f
fT
t
T
f
F
T
T
tT
t
tF
f
F
t
F
F
T
tF
f
tT
t
F
t
33
lOMoARcPSD|359747 69
11/1/2016
18
Argument:
~(pq),
(q v r)
(qp)
Valid
because the
only row with
true premises
also has a true
conclusion
34
p
q
r
~(pq)*
(q v r)*
(qp) (C)
--
-
--
-
--
-
----------
-------
-------
T
T
T
F
t
tT
t
tT
t
T
T
F
F
t
tT
f
tT
t
T
F
T
T
f
fT
t
fT
t
T
F
F
T
f
fF
f
fT
t
F
T
T
F
t
tT
t
tF
f
F
T
F
F
t
tT
f
tF
f
F
F
T
F
t
fT
t
fT
f
F
F
F
F
t
fF
f
fT
f
| 1/18

Preview text:

lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016 Critical Thinking Chapter 10 A Little Propositional Logic
Lecture Notes © 2008 McGraw Hill Higher 1 Education Propositional logic
It is often difficult to determine whether a long and
complex argument is valid or invalid just by reading it. Example:
 If the Democrat loses the Senate race, the Republicans
will have a majority in the Senate.
 If the Republicans have a majority in the Senate, the
Senate will vote down the new bill.
 It is not the case that the Senate will vote down the
new bill or the Democrat will lose the Senate race.
 So, it is not the case that if the Democrat does not lose,
the Senate will not vote down the new bill 2 1 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016 Symbolization
Propositional logic is the way to symbolize the parts of
arguments so that we can analyze the whole arguments for validity.
When you symbolize an argument, you represent its
simple statements with single letters, and then represent
the relationship between them (that the argument suggests) with symbols. 3 Symbolization
Example: If Bush won we’re all going to die. Bush won.
Therefore we are all going to die.
 Where:  b = Bush won  d = We’re all going to die 
The argument gets symbolized like this: 1. b d 2. b 3. d “ ” means “Therefore” 4 2 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016
Conjunction and validity
When two simple statements are conjoined with an
“and,” we call it a “conjunction.” 
We represent each statement as a simple letter,
and represent the “and” with an “&.” Example: 
“Tina is tall and Sarah is tall.” gets symbolized like
this: p & q p = Tina is tall  q = Sarah is tall 5
Other words for “and”
 If you see any of the following words, treat them like
“and” and symbolize the statement with an “&”:
 but, yet, while, whereas, although, though, however.
They are different in meanings, but functionally similar.
 Note: What letter you give it really doesn’t matter, just
as long as you are consistent (use the same letter for
that statement every time) and don’t use the same
letter for two different statements in the same argument. 3 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016 6
Other words for “and”
 Be warned: not every statement with “and” in it is compound.
Example: The Knicks and Bulls are playing each other.
 This is not expressing the facts that each team is playing…
 Mistake: The Knicks are playing and the Bulls are
playing (i.e., k & b).
 …it is expressing the single fact that the two teams are playing each other.
 So it would just get a single letter, for instance, “e.” 7 Truth Tables
 When evaluating validity, you don’t worry
about the truth value of the statements you are symbolizing.
 But each statement is either true or false (you just don’t know which).
 Truth Tables allow you to evaluate statements
and arguments without knowing truth values 4 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016
by representing all possible truth value combinations. 8 Truth Tables
 Recal , we symbolized “Tina is tal and Sarah is tal ” as “p&q”.
 We don’t know if they are or not, but we can represent all possibilities this way: p q p&q
---------- ---------- --------- - T T T T F F F T F F F F
Notice: what “p&q” means is “both p and q are true.” This means that, unless both p and
q are true, “p&q” wil not be true. That is why, above, p&q has a T only on the row on 9
which both p and q both have a T as well.
Using Truth Tables to Examine Validity  Since….
 …an argument is invalid only when it is possible for its
premises to be true and the conclusion false… …and
since truth tables show us all possible truth values
…we can use truth tables to evaluate validity.
 We use them to determine all the possible truth
values, and then look for a row where all the
premise are true but the conclusion is false. If 5 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016
we find one, the argument is invalid If there is
no such row, the argument is valid. 10 Example  (1) Tina is tall.  (2) Sarah is tall.
 (3) Therefore, Tina and Sarah are tall. Symbolized: p, q. q.
First, represent all the statement letters and their truth values. p q Notice: -----
------ First row: two T’s, two F’s, -
Second row: one T, one F (repeat) T T T F 11 F T F F Example
Then, add the premises and the conclusion. p q p* q* p&q (C) ------ ------
---------- ---------- ---------- T T T F F T 6 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016 F F 12 Example
Then, add the truth values. p q p* q* p&q (C) ------ ------
---------- ---------- ---------- T T T T T T F T F F F T F T F F F F F F 13 Example
Then look for rows where the premises are all true, and see if the
conclusion is false on those rows. If there is such a row, then the
argument is invalid. In this case, the only row with all true
premises is one in which the conclusion is also true. Thus, the argument is valid. 7 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016 p q p*  q* Va lid p&q (C) ----- ----- --------- --------- ---------- - - - - T T T T T T F T F F F T F T F F F F F F 14 More Examples 1. Grass is green. 2.
Therefore, grass is green and the sky is blue. Symbolized: g g & s g s g* g&s (c) ------ ------ ------ ------  T T T T Shows T F T F it to be invalid F T F F F F F F Since, on the second row, the premise is
true but the conclusion is false, the argument is 15 invalid. 8 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016 Negation
 We can easily represent “negated statements” with a “~” (tilde).
 If “Sarah is tall” is “p” “Sarah is not tall” is
“~p” On a truth table:  anywhere p has a T  ~p will have an F 16 Example:
 (1) Tina is not Tall, but Sarah is tall. So, Tina is not tall.  Symbolized: ~p, q ~p p q ~p* q* ~p (C) ----- ----- --------- --------- --------- - - - - - T T F T F T F F F F F T T T T Valid F F T F T
The argument is valid. The only row on which both premises are true is a row on which the conclusion is also true. 17 9 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016 Another example
Argument: Frank does not drive a truck. Therefore,
Frank doesn’t drive a truck and Vinny doesn’t drive a
minivan. Symbolized: ~f ~f & ~v ~f* ~ ( f & ~v) (c ) f v ~v ---------- ---------- --- --- --- F f F f T T F F f F t T F T T t Finvalid f T F T F t T t F F T
Argument is invalid. Row 3 is an example of a row with true premises but a false 18 conclusion.
Whole statement negations
 Not only can individual statements be negated: ~p
 Compound statements can be too: ~(p&q)
 Since “p&q” means “Both p and q are true”
“~(p&q)” means “It is false that both p and q are true.” 19 10 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016
Whole statement negations
 But don’t distribute (like in math): ~(p&q) is not the same as (~p & ~q)  Why?
 ~(p&q) means they are not both true (at least one is false)
 (~p & ~q) means they are both false 20
Proof: ~(p&q) ≠ (~p & ~q) p q ~p ~q p&q ~ (p&q) ~p & ~q ---- ---- ---- ---- ---- ---- ----- T T F F T F F T F F T F T F F T T F F T F F F T T F T T 21 11 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016
Truth tables with 3 variables (set up) Notice: p q r
Third column, one T, one F (repeat) ---- ----
---- Second column, two T’s, Two F’s (repeat) First column, T T T four T’s, four F’s T T F T F T T F F F T T F T F 22 F F T F F F 12 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016
Argument: ~(p&q), (~q&r) ~p p q r ~(p&q)* ( ~q & r )* ~p (c)
--- --- --- ----------- ---------------- ------------ T T T F f F F t t T T F F f F F t f T F T T F  Shows it f t T t is invalid T F F T F f t F f F T T T f F T f t F T F T f F T f f F F T T T  Even f t T t though F F F T t F T 24 f f
Disjunctions (or statements)
“Frank is angry or Hank is tired.” gets symbolized: a v t
(To make things easier, don’t ever use the letter “v”
to symbolize a simple statement.) Exclusive and inclusive “or”:
Exclusive or: “a or b” means “a or b, but not both.”
Inclusive or: “a or b” means “at least a or b, but maybe both.”
The convention is to use the inclusive sense. So…. 25 13 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016
Disjunction truth tables p q pvq --- --- ---- T T T T F T F T T F F F 26 Argument: pvq p p q pvq* p (C) --- --- ---- ---- T T T T T F T T F T T F  Invalid F F F F 27 14 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016
Be careful with negations of disjunctions
 Frank is angry or Hank is tired. a v t
 Frank is not angry or Hank is tired. ~a v t
 Frank is not angry or Hank is not tired. ~a v ~t
It’s not the case that Frank is angry or Hank is tired. ~(a v t)
Neither is Frank angry nor is Hank tired. ~(a v t)
These last two are the same as “Frank is not angry and Hank is not tired.” (~a & ~t) 28
Proof: ~(pvq) ~p&~q p q ~(pvq) ~p&~q --- --- -------- -------- - T T F t fFf T F F t fFt F T F t tFf F F T f tTt 29 look they match 15 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016 Conditional (if, then) statements
“If it rained then the ground is wet.” Where:  r = it rained
 w = the ground is wet r w “r” is the antecedent “w” is the consequent
Lecture Notes © 2008 McGraw Hill Higher 30 Education
Conditional truth tables
 Truth table is tricky. “pq” means
“every time p is true, q is true.” p q pq
 Or “when p is true, q is true.” --- --- ------
 So, only when the antecedent is true and the T T T consequent false, is it the 
case that the conditional is false. T F F
 If this confuses you, don’t worry… It is confusing. Just remember it. F T T 31 F F T 16 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016
Be careful with negation and conditionals
 If it did not rain, then the game was played.  ~rp
 If it did not rain, then the game was not played.  ~r ~p
 It is not the case that, if it rained then the game was played.  ~(rp)
 These all have different meanings. 32
Be careful with negation and conditionals p
q pq ~pq ~p~q ~(pq) --
--- ----- -------- --------- ---------- - T T T fTt fTf F t T F F fTf fTt T f F T T tTt tFf F t F F T tFf tTt F t 33 17 lOMoARcPSD|359 747 69 11/1/2016 Argument: ~(pq), p q r
~(pq)* (q v r)* (qp) (C) (q v r) -- -- -- ---------- ------- ------- (qp) - - - T T T F t tTt tTt T T F F t tTf tTt T F T T f fTt fTt T F F T f fFf fTt Valid because the F T T F t tTt tFf only row with true premises F T F F t tTf tFf also has a true conclusion F F T F t fTt fTf 34 F F F F t fFf fTf 18
Document Outline

  • Propositional logic
  • Symbolization
  • Symbolization (1)
  • Conjunction and validity
  • Other words for “and”
  • Other words for “and” (1)
  • Truth Tables
  • Truth Tables (1)
  • Using Truth Tables to Examine Validity
  • Example
  • Example (1)
  • Example (2)
  • Example (3)
  • More Examples
  • Negation
  • Another example
  • Whole statement negations
  • Whole statement negations (1)
  • Proof: ~(p&q) ≠ (~p & ~q)
  • Truth tables with 3 variables (set up)
  • Argument: ~(p&q), (~q&r) ~p
  • Disjunctions (or statements)
  • Disjunction truth tables
  • Argument: pvq p
  • Be careful with negations of disjunctions
  • Proof: ~(pvq)  ~p&~q
  • Conditional (if, then) statements
  • Conditional truth tables
  • Be careful with negation and conditionals
  • Be careful with negation and conditionals (1)
  • ~(pq), (q v r)  (qp)